Galilei, Galileo, De Motu Antiquiora

List of thumbnails

< >
21
21
22
22
23
23
24
24
25
25
26
26
27
27
28
28
29
29
30
30
< >
page |< < of 161 > >|
326 but it will never happen that this equality lasts for any length of time whatever, since the one motion is continuously weakened but the other is continuously intensified: hence, necessarily, c will switch from one motion to its contrary, without the intervention of any rest. A third argument can be taken from a certain rectilinear motion that Nicholas Copernicus in his De Revolutionibus compounds from two circular motions. For they are two circles, one of which is carried on the circumference of the other, and when one is moved more swiftly than the other, a mark on the circumference (of the slower?) is carried along a straight line and runs back and forth along it continuously; and yet it cannot be said that it is at rest at the extremities, since it is continually carried around by the circumference of the circle. {1} [see also my notes below]But the adversaries, in order to escape from this, say that the large stone is at rest, and thus they persuade themselves that they have done enough for the argument. But, so that in the future (unless they should be downright obstinate) they may not believe this, I shall add this to the argument: let these stones, which are moved by contrary motions, be carried, not upward and downward, but on a plane surface parallel to the horizon, one with great impetus, but the other more slowly, and let them be moved from contrary positions in contrary directions; and let them converge in the middle in an interacting motion: in that case the weaker will undoubtedly be thrust back by the stronger and will be compelled to be carried in the opposite direction; but how will they say that at that point of impact a rest intervenes? For if only once they were at rest, they would thereafter always be at rest, since they would have no cause for moving, as in the case of that large stone, coming from on high: if it were stopped by the pebble, still after the rest, they would both go down in concordance, moved by their proper heaviness; but when they are on a plane parallel to the horizon, after the rest, there is no cause for motion after the rest. Here is a last argument: before its explication let these two things be presupposed. First, I presuppose that a mobile can be at rest outside its proper place only when the force impeding its descent is equal to its heaviness, which exerts pressure downward: which surely is manifest; for if the impressed force were greater than the resisting heaviness, the mobile

Search results

< >
Searching "tower" (fulltextMorph)
1. Page 16, Sentence 4:How ridiculous this opinion is, is clearer than daylight: for who will ever believe that if, for example, two lead balls were released from the sphere of the Moon, one being a hundred times larger than the other, if the larger took an hour to come to Earth, the smaller would use in its motion a space of time of a hundred hours? or, if from a high tower {1}, two stones, one being double the size of the other, were thrown at the same moment, that, when the smaller was at mid-tower, the larger would already have reached the ground?
2. Page 24, Sentence 18:For if one takes two different mobiles, which have such properties that one is carried twice as swiftly as the other, and then releases them from the top of a tower, it will certainly not hit the ground faster, twice as swiftly: what is more, if one makes the observation, the one which is lighter at the beginning of the motion will precede the heavier and will be faster.
3. Page 68, Sentence 9:But this way of thinking is not only false, but ridiculous: for, if it were true, it would follow that a stone going down from a very high tower would be moved more slowly at mid-tower, than if the same stone were falling to the ground from a very low place, and for this reason the mobile [falling from a greater height] would also make a lesser impact.
4. Page 76, Sentence 3:There is a fourth well-known argument concerning a large stone going down from a tower, which will not be sufficiently blocked by a pebble impelled upward by force, so as to permit the pebble to be at rest for any time: hence surely the pebble will not be at rest at the ultimate point of its upward motion, and Aristotle notwithstanding, it will make use of the ultimate point for the two limits, namely of upward motion and of downward motion; and the ultimate instant is taken twice, namely, for the end of one time and for the beginning of the other.
5. Page 79, Sentence 4:Now in the case of heavier things, since a great amount of contrary force must be consumed in their descent, a greater time will be required for it to be consumed; in which time, since they are carried swiftly, they will descend a great distance: since we cannot avail ourselves of such great distances from which to release heavy things, it is not astonishing if the stone, released from merely the height of a tower, will seem to accelerate all the way to the ground; for this short distance and short time of motion are not sufficient to destroy the whole contrary force.
6. Page 84, Sentence 6:Yet experience shows the contrary: for it is true that wood at the beginning of its motion is carried more speedily than lead; but a little later the motion of lead is so accelerated that it leaves the wood behind, and, if they are released from a high tower, the lead gets ahead of it by a large distance: and I have often put this to the test. {1}
7. Page 134, Sentence 6:But if we go up a very high tower, on the top of which there is a bathtub, the same thing will happen to us when in it as if we were to go into the sea: for we will not be weighed down by the water, even though the latter, having air underneath it, is outside its proper place.
8. Page 150, Sentence 12:For if a stone goes down from a high tower, its swiftness seems always to be increased: yet this happens because the stone, in comparison /// with the medium through which it is carried, namely air, is very heavy; and since it goes away with an amount of impressed force as great as its heaviness, it assuredly goes away with a great impressed force, which the motion from the height of a tower is not sufficient to consume, so that the swiftness is always intensified all through the height of a single tower.

Text layer

  • Dictionary
  • Search results
  • Places

Text normalization

  • Original
  • Regularized
  • Normalized

Search


Clear
  • Exact
  • All forms
  • Fulltext index
  • Morphological index